Metaethics

Basic Information

Course modules 2023/2024
Lecturer
Ryan P. Doran
Semester
1st.
Department
Department of Philosophy
University
Universitat de Barcelona
Module
Module 1. Practical Philosophy
Code
570624
Credits
5
Language
English

Dates

Schedule
Thursdays, 10:00 - 13:00
Location
Classroom 409, Faculty of Philosophy, Universitat de Barcelona

Description

Metaethics is concerned with the metaphysical and epistemological status of moral thought—i.e., thought about what one ought or ought not to do, or about what is morally good or bad

—and with the language we use to communicate such thoughts to others. The overall aim of the course is to familiarize you with the main issues and positions in contemporary metaethics, and to give you the tools that allow you to offer reasoned arguments for your own views on the central questions.

The course begins with two questions to which many positions in the 20th and 21st century metaethics may be seen as responding. The first is G. E. Moore’s famous ‘open question’ argument, which purports to show that moral properties cannot be defined in a nonmoral way. The second is what Michael Smith calls the ‘moral problem’, that is, the problem of reconciling the apparent objectivity of moral judgements, viz. their representing a mind-independent reality, with their apparent practicality.

The course assesses various reactions to both questions. Noncognitivists, represented by Ayer and Blackburn, emphasize the practicality of moral judgement, and deny that moral thought and language even aim to pick out real properties in the first place.

Error-theorists, represented by Mackie, say that moral thought aims to picks out real properties, but they also say that there are no suitable properties for our moral thoughts to pick out. So, our moral judgments are, strictly speaking, false even though practically useful. Moral realists say that moral thoughts aim to pick out real properties, and that they often succeed. Dispositionalism and constructivism, finally, are alternative approaches that can be developed in both subjectivist and objectivist directions.

Considerations from metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of language are all relevant in making sense of, and deciding between, these different positions.

Week

    1. Week 1 – Overview of metaethics
    2. Week 2 – The Open Question Argument

Moore, G. E. (1903/1959). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chapter 1.

    1. Week 3 – The Moral Problem

Smith, M. (1995). The Moral Problem. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, chapter 1.

    1. Week 4 – Simple noncognitivism

Ayer, A. J. (1936/1971). Language, Truth and Logic. London: Penguin, chapter 6.

    1. Week 5 – Cognitivism without realism

Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin, chapter 1.

    1. Week 6 – Subtle noncognitivism

Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press, chapter 6.

    1. Week 7 – Cognitivism with realism

Railton, P. (1986). Moral realism. The Philosophical Review, 95(2), 163–207.

Scanlon, T. M. (2003). Metaphysics and morals. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 77(2), 7–22.

    1. Week 8 – Dispositionalism and constructivism

Lewis, D. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 63, 113–137.

    1. Internal vs. external reasons I

Williams, B. (1979/1981). Internal and external reasons. In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980 (pp. 101–113). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    1. Internal vs. external reasons II

Foot, P. (1972). Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. The Philosophical Review, 81(3), 305–316.

    1. Realism and evolution

Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109–166.

 

Learning outcomes

Basic skills:

CB6 – Students should be able to critically understand central texts in the field of metaethics in a way that puts them in a position to develop and apply original ideas.

CB9 - Students should be able to communicate their knowledge and their arguments to specialized audiences in a clear and articulate way.

General skills:

CG2. Students should be able to design, create, develop, and undertake new and innovative projects in their area of interest.

CG3. Students should be able to engage both in general and specific discussions in the domain of metaethics. They should be able to conduct a philosophical discussion (orally and in written form) by putting forward, for example, general arguments or specific examples in support of their position.

CG4. Students should be able to work both independently as well as in a team, in an international environment.

CG5. Students should be able to identify methodological errors, rhetorical, conventional, and uncritical assumptions.

 

Specific skills:

CE1. Students should be able to critically engage with the concepts and methods of contemporary metaethics and practice the competent application of these notions in a philosophical debate.

CE2. Students should be able to identify the core arguments and theories of contemporary metaethics.

CE4. Students should be able to assess the writings of leading contemporary philosophers in the field of metaethics.

CE5. Students should be able to identify and critically engage with the current state of a particular philosophical debate and form a reasoned view, even if provisional, about it.

CE7. Students should be able to critically use specialized terminology in the field of metaethics.

 

 

Learning objectives

Referring to knowledge

The aim of the course is to familiarize participants with the main issues and positions in the contemporary metaethical debate, and to give them the tools to begin to defend a view of their own.

More specifically, this includes:

Understanding the main positions in the metaethical debate of the 20th and 21st century. Understanding most of the key notions and arguments used in this debate.

Practicing the competent application of these notions in a philosophical debate.

Developing the ability to articulate one’s own position in this debate (at least provisionally) and to defend it in argument.

This contributes to the following competences promoted by the APhil master programme:

The competent use of the terminology, concepts, and methods used in contemporary analytic philosophy, and their employment in the argumentative defense of a position.

The ability to identify the current state of a particular philosophical debate and form a reasoned view, even if provisional, about it.

The ability to conduct a philosophical discussion (orally and in written form) by putting forward, for example, general arguments or specific examples, in support of one’s position.

The ability to work independently as well as in a team, in an international environment.

The independent and creative application of one’s knowledge to new problems, i.e., the ability to employ knowledge and abilities acquired in one area in order to address new problems or problems in different areas.

The ability to conduct philosophical research in an independent and autonomous way (as is required, for example, in pursuing doctoral studies).

 

Methodology

There will be a two-and-a-half-hour class each week. Each class will consist of a seminar in which we will discuss the assigned reading of the day. It is expected that students study the assigned texts carefully in advance and prepare a summary and discussion questions. Attendance is obligatory. The assigned texts will be available online.

 

 

Evaluation

Seminars

The seminars will take place each week starting from week 2. They will involve discussion in small groups, focused on the assigned reading.

What do I need to do to prepare for the seminar?

Before each seminar, you are required to:

  • Read the paper.
  • Complete your assignment.
  • Bring a copy of the paper and of the assignment to the seminar.

What is the assignment for the seminar? The assignment involves two parts:

  1. One or more questions that you have about the paper. Questions can be specific or general, and of any kind (about something that you don’t understand, something that you think doesn’t work, etc.).
  2. A written exercise about the paper you read. This needs to (1) be 200 words or more (no worries if it’s a little bit less!); (2) demonstrate that you have read and understood the paper, and (3) serve as a point of reference to the discussion in class. What you write in the assignment is totally up to you. It can be a summary of the paper, but it can also be a critical discussion of one of its sections or of a minor question it raises. It can be written as a microessay, or simply as a list of bullet points that summarize the paper. But it can also be something more creative: a fake review or report, a story, or a creative piece of writing—as long as you satisfy conditions (1), (2), and (3) listed above. Be creative if you feel like it, or stick to a short summary of the article if you prefer a more traditional approach.

 

The deadline for the assignment is the night before each seminar. These exercises are worth 50% of your final mark.

 

Final essay

Your final examination will involve the redaction of a short essay. You will be required to prepare an original piece of work under 3000 words. Potential essay topics include any of the subjects discussed during the seminars, and towards the end of the course I will provide you with some sample questions to help you to identify a topic for your essay.

Students have the right to a half-hour tutorial to discuss their essay plans. Tutorials will take place 2–3 weeks before the essay deadline (available slots will be communicated in due time). You will need to send me a draft or outline of the essay at least 3 days (72 hours) in advance of the meeting. No tutorial will be granted to students failing to do so.

Essays must be submitted electronically, by sending them to ryan.p.doran@ub.edu.

The university has a strict policy on plagiarism and unfair means. Please refer to this link for more information on this.

Deadlines

Tutorial meeting arrangement: last seminar

Draft for tutorial: 3 days (72 hours) in advance of the meeting

Final essay submission deadline: TBA (around mid-December)

 

Assessment criteria

The final mark will be based on active participation in the seminars, the assignments, and the final essay.

Class participation and seminar assignments: 50%. Final essay: 50%

These may be adapted depending on sanitary recommendations from health authorities and university.

 

In order to be entitled to reevaluation, a student who fails the course has to get at least 3.

 

Bibliography

Book

Ayer, A. J. (1936/1971). Language, Truth and Logic. London: Penguin.

Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin.

Moore, G. E. (1903/1959). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Smith, M. (1995). The Moral Problem. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

 

Chapter

Williams, B. (1979/1981). Internal and external reasons. In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973– 1980 (pp. 101–113). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

 

Article

Foot, P. (1972). Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. The Philosophical Review, 81(3), 305– 316.

Lewis, D. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 63, 113–137.

Railton, P. (1986). Moral realism. The Philosophical Review, 95(2), 163–207.

Scanlon, T. M. (2003). Metaphysics and morals. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 77(2), 7–22.

Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109– 166.

 

Other considerations

If the situation requires it, the teaching plan may be adapted for virtual teaching and any modification will be promptly communicated to the students.

En aplicació del Pla d’igualtat de la Universitat de Barcelona, el contingut de l’assignatura (blocs temàtics, o temes, o problemes; bibliografia; treballs) incorpora en la mesura del possible i en funció del temari desplegat per cada professor qüestions sobre gènere (problemes, pensadores, bibliografia).